Laman

Feynman As Well As The Epr Positronium Experiment

After a struggle that lasted a calendar month or two, I understood that a really unlike quantum framework of physics was needed when I was sixteen or 17. During that struggle, I was trying to consummate a programme outlined past times Einstein – to pull all atomic phenomena using a model that was basically a classical champaign theory of a sort. I had diverse tricks to explicate the quantization of the accuse inwards damage of topological invariants – simple particles were solitons (especially skyrmions, in addition to they were wormholes of diverse topologies before that). But to explicate the hydrogen atom, I needed to bag ideas from ordinary textbooks of quantum mechanics (I started amongst those for engineers) in addition to subsequently some moment, it became clear that I needed to bag all of quantum mechanics in addition to the right probabilistic interpretation was so forced upon me because of a few curt penetrating thoughts.

So when I was kickoff exposed to the Feynman Lectures inwards Physics – a volume based on Feynman's 1964 course of teaching for Caltech undergraduates – in addition to saw his no-nonsense explanations of quantum mechanics etc., I had already been "converted". But it was all the same refreshing in addition to insightful to run into how he dealt amongst the problems. Incidentally, the edition of the lectures that I could learn was written inwards Slovak (Feynman became a partly Slovak guy inwards my optics forever LOL) – it existed many years before the Czech translation – in addition to the Slovak edition had v volumes instead of 3 volumes of the master copy edition.

In the previous weblog post, the primary physical province of affairs that created lots of discussions was Feynman's observation of superpositions establish inwards the benzene molecule. Caltech has made the whole Feynman lectures available inwards the web form.




All the "detailed" explanations of quantum mechanics appear inwards Volume III. Unlike most of the ordinary textbooks of quantum mechanics that start amongst the infinite-dimensional Hilbert spaces of particles moving inwards space, Feynman started amongst finite-dimensional (and peculiarly two-dimensional) Hilbert spaces, situations that are "typically" quantum mechanical.

One may tell that amongst the assist of these examples, Feynman taught things that "don't receive got similar plenty classical counterparts" that could mislead the students. So this is arguably a ameliorate way to brand the students retrieve quantum mechanically. The examples of 2-dimensional Hilbert spaces are analyzed inwards chapters 8-12 of the volume. For example, Section 10.4 describes the molecule of benzene.

Feynman never uses the tidings "entangled" or "entanglement" inwards the 1964 lectures – fifty-fifty though the words were coined past times Schrödinger inwards 1935-1936, as less ludicrous synonyms of Einstein's 1935 term "spooky activeness at a distance". I believe that he just establish these extra words unnecessary (like the "name of the bird", the tidings teaches us nothing) – in addition to he didn't desire to usage words that receive got often appeared inwards monologues of folks similar Schrödinger who said many right things but also many wrong things.




He also avoided the tidings "qubit" – inwards this instance because the tidings wasn't genuinely about inwards 1964 yet. But it's obvious that all his discussions of 2-dimensional Hilbert spaces are possible realizations of a qubit.

Here, I desire to pass some fourth dimension amongst Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen (EPR) newspaper nigh the quantum entanglement (again, Feynman has avoided this tidings everywhere).

The kickoff "difference of style" you lot must notice is that spell EPR discussed "just the full general issue" of the entangled objects, Feynman picked a real-world instance amongst all the details so that you lot could genuinely apply it to a existent experiment. Feynman has always preferred to retrieve inwards damage of really explicit examples. As long as i realizes that the lessons in addition to methods generalize to many similar examples (and Feynman did realize that), I retrieve it's ameliorate to focus on really specific examples.

To verbalize over entanglement, Feynman picked the decay of the positronium, a outpouring terra firma of \(e^-\) in addition to \(e^+\). It looks just similar the hydrogen atom except that the proton \(p\) is replaced past times the as positively charged positron \(e^+\). The relevant employment for the "relative coordinate" is isomorphic to the hydrogen employment except that the reduced majority is\[

\mu = \frac{m_e m_p}{m_e+m_p} = \frac{m_e^2}{2m_e} = \frac{m_e}{2}

\] assuming that the subscript \(p\) denotes the positron. This reduced majority is just half of the reduced majority for the ordinary hydrogen, to a greater extent than or less \(m_e\), which is why in that location are many factors-of-two inserted relatively to the hydrogen atom. For example, the Blue Planet terra firma has unloosen energy \(-6.8\eV\) instead of \(-13.6\eV\) of the hydrogen atom.

As you lot know, the electron wants to annihilate amongst the positron. How quickly?

This is an number non direct relevant for the EPR considerations – in addition to Feynman analyzes the relative spins elsewhere – but the positronium may receive got the same spins of the ii fermions, or opposite ones. If the spins are opposite, the resulting outpouring terra firma is a singlet terra firma amongst \(S=0\), the para-positronium. It almost ever decays to ii photons in addition to the parity of the outpouring terra firma is negative, \(P=-1\). The lifetime is 124 picoseconds.

There's also a triplet state, the ortho-positronium, where the fermions receive got the same spin in addition to the total is hence \(S=1\) in addition to the parity is positive, \(P=+1\). It's much to a greater extent than long-lived, 139 nanoseconds, in addition to decays mostly to 3 photons.

We volition verbalize over the singlet state, the para-positronium, in addition to its decay to ii photons. Feynman apace deduces that the terra firma of these ii photons (flying inwards opposite directions) is\[

\ket{F} = \frac{\ket{R_1 R_2} - \ket{L_1 L_2}}{\sqrt{2}}

\] He omits the factor of \(1/\sqrt{2}\) that nosotros commonly include. It's just a unlike convention: it's non "wrong" to piece of work amongst ket vectors non normalized to unity. Note that both photons, flight to detectors \(1\) in addition to \(2\), receive got the same round down polarization, \(L\) or \(R\). The total spin has to live null but ii \(R\) photons flight to the opposite directions genuinely receive got the opposite angular momentum (the angular momentum has the sign of the \(L/R\) helicity times the ordinary momentum in addition to the ordinary momenta are opposite) which add together upward to zero, so it's OK. (Similarly for ii \(L\) photons.) And the relative sign or stage inwards betwixt the ii damage is \((-1)\) because \[

P\ket F = \frac{\ket{L_1 L_2} - \ket{R_1 R_2}}{\sqrt{2}} = -\ket F.

\] The parity of the two-photon terra firma is negative – the parity is conserved which is why it has to live equal to the negative parity of the master copy positronium state. Note that the parity is a "mirror reflection" (the determinant is negative) in addition to the right-handed screw is hence changed to the left-handed one. The coefficients were unchanged.

Excellent. So nosotros may run into the quantum mechanical predictions for the round down polarization. When the two-photon state\[

\ket{F} =\frac{ \ket{R_1 R_2} - \ket{L_1 L_2}}{\sqrt{2}}.

\] is measured to bring out the round down polarization, nosotros run into that if the photon \(1\) is \(R\), so is the photon \(2\), or both of them may live left-handed \(L\), if the 2d term is realized. The correlation betwixt the round down polarizations is "perfect" as guaranteed past times the angular momentum conservation law. Even people similar EPR who didn't genuinely believe quantum mechanics would tend to concur that the angular momentum conservation police clit agency that alone \(RR\) or \(LL\) were possible if the round down polarizations are measured.

Fine. So the existent argument alone arises when nosotros create upward one's hear to mensurate the linear polarizations of both photons – whether their electrical fields oscillate inwards the \(x\) management or the \(y\) management (the electrical champaign "names" the polarization past times convention; the magnetic champaign oscillates along the other axis). To bring out the right quantum mechanical predictions for these measurements of \(x,y\) polarizations, nosotros merely convert \(\ket F\) from the circularly polarized footing to the linearly polarized basis.

We attain it easily amongst the conversion formulae inwards betwixt the bases:\[

\sqrt{2}\ket {R_1} = \ket{x_1} + i\ket{y_1}\\
\sqrt{2}\ket {L_1} = \ket{x_1} - i\ket{y_1}\\

\] and\[

\sqrt{2}\ket {R_2} = \ket{x_2} + i\ket{y_2}\\
\sqrt{2}\ket {L_2} = \ket{x_2} - i\ket{y_2}\\

\] The green equations are obtained past times dividing these past times \(\sqrt{2}\), I just wanted to relieve some space. The right-handed polarized photon is a superposition of the ii linearly polarized ones, amongst the 90-degree stage shift guaranteed past times the coefficient \(i\). The relative stage is opposite for the left-handed polarization.

With the green conventions nigh axes etc., nosotros may live able to figure out which is \(R\) in addition to which is \(L\), but fifty-fifty if nosotros confused the two, it wouldn't live a big bargain because \(F\) is antisymmetric amongst abide by to \(R\) in addition to \(L\), anyway (and produces the same probabilities for them, so if nosotros confuse \(R\) in addition to \(L\) everywhere, it changes nil nigh predictions for \(x,y\)). You mightiness live worried that it's really of import whether nosotros usage the same relative phases for the photon \(2\) as nosotros did for the photon \(1\). But this number is genuinely also unimportant because a sign error may live included to a redefinition of the sign of \(\ket{y_2}\). Moreover, it's possible to extrapolate the relative phases so that "the convention is the same everywhere" past times connecting the ii photons' momenta via a 180-degree rotation about the \(y\)-axis.

As long as you lot believe that it's possible to write the conversion from \(\ket{R,L}\) to \(\ket{x,y}\) that has a existent coefficient betwixt \(R\) in addition to \(x\) in addition to betwixt \(L\) in addition to \(x\) in addition to the signs are the same betwixt \(R,L\) for a given photon, the sign conventions inwards a higher house are basically OK. With these formulae, it's slowly to rewrite the two-photon terra firma \(\ket F\) to the \(x,y\) bases for the photon.

It is non difficult to run into that inwards the departure \(\ket{RR}-\ket{LL}\), the damage \(\ket{xx}\) cancel betwixt \(\ket{RR}\) in addition to \(\ket{LL}\), in addition to so attain the damage \(\ket{yy}\). On the contrary, the mixed damage \(\ket{xy}\) in addition to \(\ket{yx}\) volition double in addition to this extra factor of ii cancels against \((\sqrt{2})^2\) from the basis-change. To summarize, nosotros get\[

\ket F = \frac{ i\ket{x_1 y_2} + i\ket{x_2 y_1} }{\sqrt{2}}

\] You run into that if i photon is \(x\)-polarized, the other i is \(y\)-polarized, in addition to vice versa. If nosotros had made some of import sign errors inwards the "change of bases" or inwards the relative sign defining the master copy \(\ket F\), nosotros could incorrectly conclude that the linear polarizations of the ii photons were the same. It wouldn't live such a huge departure for the piece of work of discussions nigh the EPR issues because what matters is that the correlation or anticorrelation would all the same live 100% spell Einstein would predict no correlation, as nosotros volition verbalize over momentarily.

Feel gratis to attain these things genuinely carefully. With the nonzero take away chances that Feynman has made a fault in addition to the linear polarizations should live 100% correlated rather than anticorrelated, allow us motility on in addition to verbalize nigh the qualitative things that genuinely matter.

What genuinely matters is that Einstein in addition to collaborators believed that the probabilities receive got to live 25%, 25%, 25%, 25% for the results of the linear polarizations \(xx,xy,yx,yy\), respectively. That differs from our quantum mechanical prediction 0%, 50%, 50%, 0%. The experiment may live performed in addition to it confirms that the correlated QM prediction is right spell EPR were wrong: Nature genuinely guarantees the perfect correlations or anticorrelations both inwards the round down polarizations in addition to inwards the linear polarizations.

Feynman summarizes the wrong Einstein-like "classical" declaration to half-dozen arguments in addition to he says that 1,2,4,6 are right spell 3,5 are wrong. The kickoff wrong supposition 3 starts past times words that audio past times "locality" but the supposition is genuinely the whole "local realism" so 3 is wrong, indeed. One could struggle that Feynman hasn't separated "locality" from "realism" as cleanly as I would. But nosotros must realize that he was basically trying to reproduce the arguments past times EPR in addition to similar folks in addition to these folks receive got sure non separated "locality" from "realism" cleanly at all. So this conflation may live said non to live Feynman's imperfection.

OK. But allow me straightaway "localize" in addition to "quantify" the actual departure betwixt the right quantum mechanical calculation; in addition to Einstein's calculation based on some "local realist" thinking. The right quantum mechanical derivation predicts the probability of \(xx\) – both photons are \(x\)-polarized – to live 0% because the coefficient inwards the ket vector \(F\) inwards front end of \(\ket{x_1x_2}\) inwards this footing is zero, OK?

On the other hand, Einstein predicts the probability to live 25%. How does it work?

Einstein assumes that the probability of \(xx\) may live calculated from the probabilities of \(RR,RL,LR,LL\) using some "classical probabilistic reasoning". This is my contribution to the analysis "how the wrong thinking works":\[

{\rm Einstein, wrong:}\\
\eq{
P(xx)&= P(xx|RR)P(RR)+P(xx|RL)P(RL)+\\
&+P(xx|LR)P(LR)+P(xx|LL)P(LL)
}

\] Each of the iv damage involves the conditional probability of \(xx\) given \(RR\), in addition to so on.

This is how the classical reasoning works. The stance is that nosotros may assume that i of the iv states described past times the round down polarization, \(RR,RL,LR,LL\), has to live objectively realized fifty-fifty if nosotros don't mensurate the round down polarization. It seems necessary to Einstein because when the kickoff photon is measured to live \(R\) in addition to nosotros know for certain that the 2d photon volition live \(R\) as well, it seems similar a proof that the 2d photon must live "objectively" \(R\) already before the measurement.

Because alone the \(RR\) in addition to \(LL\) states of the round down polarization are allowed, Einstein's reasoning reduces to\[

\eq{
P(xx) &= P(xx|RR)P(RR)+P(xx|LL)P(LL)\\
& = \frac xiv \cdot \frac 12 + \frac xiv \cdot \frac 12= \frac 14.
}

\] The probability merely has to live 25% if relativity is true, Einstein thought. However, the calculation inwards a higher house assumes non alone locality but also "realism". As Feynman also points out, Einstein incorrectly assumes that the enquiry "whether the photons are inwards \(RR,RL,LR\) or \(LL\)" has a precipitous reply fifty-fifty if nosotros don't mensurate the round down polarization. But this is merely non true. Questions nigh properties of objects mostly alone receive got precipitous answers if the answers are measured past times an actual measurement. It matters whether an observer genuinely observes something or not.

So the calculation using the conditional probabilities inwards a higher house is incorrect. Is in that location a way to "fix it past times a localized fix"? Yes, in that location is. The right quantum mechanical calculation that determines the probability of \(xx\) is genuinely very similar to Einstein's wrong calculation using the conditional probabilities above. But it differs from the "formula amongst iv terms" inwards i respect: nosotros receive got to calculate the probability amplitudes, non the probabilities themselves, in addition to alone calculate the probabilities at the really halt out of the probability amplitudes.

Let me repeat the wrong Einstein's four-term calculation of the probability using the conditional probabilities:\[

\eq{
P(xx)&= P(xx|RR)P(RR)+P(xx|RL)P(RL)+\\
&+P(xx|LR)P(LR)+P(xx|LL)P(LL)
}

\] The right quantum mechanical formula for the corresponding probability aAmplitude is really similar:\[

\eq{
\langle twenty \ket F &= \langle twenty \ket {RR} \bra {RR} F \rangle + \langle twenty \ket {RL} \bra {RL} F \rangle\\
&+\langle twenty \ket {LR} \bra {LR} F \rangle + \langle twenty \ket {LL} \bra {LL} F \rangle
}

\] Where does it come upward from? I receive got merely "sandwiched" the completeness relation\[

1 = \ket {RR} \bra {RR} + \ket {RL} \bra {RL} +\ket {LR} \bra {LR} + \ket {LL} \bra {LL}

\] inwards betwixt \(\bra {xx}\) in addition to \(\ket F\). This "sandwiching" had the outcome of converting the known probability amplitudes stored inwards the terra firma vector \(\ket F\) from the circularly polarized bases to the linearly polarized bases.

But my right quantum mechanical formula is really analogous to Einstein's because the right Born formula for the quantum mechanical probability is\[

P_{QM}(xx) = \abs{ \langle twenty \ket F }^2

\] in addition to similarly\[

P_{QM}(RR) = \abs{ \langle RR \ket F }^2

\] in addition to so on. The probability is just the squared absolute value of the probability amplitude. So what Einstein wanted to live calculated is just the squared absolute value of \(\langle twenty \ket F\). However, when nosotros foursquare the absolute value of this right aAmplitude which I copy-and-paste hither again,\[

\eq{
\langle twenty \ket F &= \langle twenty \ket {RR} \bra {RR} F \rangle + \langle twenty \ket {RL} \bra {RL} F \rangle\\
&+\langle twenty \ket {LR} \bra {LR} F \rangle + \langle twenty \ket {LL} \bra {LL} F \rangle,
}

\] nosotros receive got to usage things similar \((A+B)^2 = A^2 +2AB+B^2\) in addition to aside from the (four) squared damage that await similar iv Einstein's terms, nosotros also learn all the (twelve) mixed damage such as \(2AB\)! These are damage that Einstein's classical derivation – i that produced \(P(xx)=1/4\) – has overlooked.

We may summarize the province of affairs past times the declaration that the "classical reasoning" assuming that objects receive got objective properties fifty-fifty if these properties are non measured is exactly equivalent to omitting all the mixed damage i.e. just equivalent to neglecting all the quantum interference!

Once you lot realize that the right predictions e.g. for the double slit experiment require the interference in addition to mixed terms, so you lot should live able to sympathise that this is equivalent to admitting that i can't assume that i of the "possible outcomes of a measurement" are objectively realized fifty-fifty inwards the absence of a measurement.

According to quantum mechanics, this is merely non the case. When a physical object is measured, i obtains a precipitous outcome – i of the eigenvalues of the corresponding operator – but just a picosecond earlier, this outcome just wasn't in addition to couldn't receive got been decided yet. If the observable isn't measured, the object finds itself inwards a superposition determined past times complex probability amplitudes in addition to the right way to interpret these probability amplitudes to predictions differs from the classical logic, i that assumes that "some properties objectively be fifty-fifty if they're non measured".

No comments:

Post a Comment